|
Bacon and Descartes on a New Beginning
…if a man
will begin with certainties, he shall end in doubts; but if he will be
content to begin with doubts, he shall end in certainties. – Francis Bacon
Despite the disparity of metaphor (Bacon speaks of “new
beginnings” and Descartes of “secure foundations”) and the inequality of
response (Bacon did nothing to compare with Descartes’ contributions to
mathematics, although his accomplishment in creating a scientific community
should not be underestimated), Bacon and Descartes were effectively
consanguineous participants in a single broad project that defined the
intellectual history of their time. Numerous individuals, most notably
Galileo and Harvey, began to engage in investigations into the workings of
nature such as, in Bacon’s words, lay practically dormant since the century
before Plato. The need appeared consequent to create an explanatory and
justificatory theory of the new sciences and also to speculate as to what
new tools - intellectual tools in Descartes’ case and social institutions in
Bacon’s - may best serve such research. Bacon's Novum Organum was
intended to provide a new method and conceptual structure for scientific
research, and at least one of Descartes' biographers views the Règles
pour la direction de l'esprit as a sort of compeittive
alternative to Bacon's approach (Clarke,
p. 86). At the very least the Règles
build upon the Novum Organum and provide much new content for the
17th century theory of the sciences. The parallelism between Descartes and
Bacon deserves comment.
- It is at first blush striking (to say the least)
that the model of the new scientific research given pride of place by both
Descartes and Bacon is Harvey’s discovery of the circulation of blood. Not
Galileo. From a chronological standpoint Galileo was internationally
celebrated by 1610 and Harvey’s research only came to fruition around 1616
or thereabouts. Over and above that, it was Galileo who first promulgated
the idea of experimental verification of theories and used measurement as
a critical tool in his gathering of observational data. In Bacon’s case
the explanation for the lacuna most likely lies in his personal relation
to Harvey and his general lack of appreciation for the importance of
measurement and mathematics in scientific theory. Descartes states bluntly
(Discours de la méthode, Part Six) that his reticence, in light of
Galileo’s condemnation by the Inquisition in 1633, was due to his desire
for peace and quiet.
- The empiricist/rationalist division makes a poor fit
when one gets down to the actual details of Bacon and Descartes’ theories.
Bacon, as much as Descartes, was concerned that research not be haphazard,
that it proceed by “fixed rules” and a “sure method.” His own wording is
that the empirical and the rational faculties must work together. He even
has some kind words about metaphysics: “…knowledge is worthiest when it is
charged with the least multiplicity; which appeareth to be Metaphysics; as
that which considereth the Simple Forms or Differences of things, which
are few in number, and the degrees and coordinations whereof make all this
variety.” (p. 197
The Advancement of Learning)
- Neither attack actual inferences from syllogistic
logic. Rather, both say that the schoolmen use obscure terms and words
that have no meaning. Bacon provides the best description of this: The
schoolmen go straight from individual instances to the broadest
generalizations, skipping the intermediate steps. Another problem is that
syllogistic logic had no mechanism for demonstrating the validity of major
premises (unless a major was also the conclusion of another syllogism).
Bacon speaks of an up and down movement where individual instances are
generalized and truths about other individual instances are arrived at
from the generalizations through deduction. Bacon (Novum
Organum p. 2: “…the first notions of things which the
mind accepts, keeps and accumulates…are faulty and confused and abstracted
from things without care….” The reference to making the mind “compliant
with nature” simply means that close observation and experiment should
never be abandoned. Descartes observes, perhaps ironically, that there may
be some pedagogic value to syllogism but that it should be set aside as
soon as one leaves school (Règles
pour la direction de l'esprit p. 40).
- Each man can lay claim to a singular (“singular”
being very broadly defined in Descartes’ case) contribution to the basic
theory and tool chest of science. Bacon’s contribution was induction as he
exemplifies in his comments on the study of heat. But what Bacon calls
induction does not consist in generalization from individual instances;
his version was nothing at all like the positivist notion of induction,
which is closer to the form Bacon attacks as mere enumeration. For
example, Bacon, repeatedly insists that true induction seeks to “separate
out a nature by appropriate rejections and exclusions. (NO p. 84)”
In the same passage he cites Plato as the best example of the inductive
method, which would be a remarkable thing were we to make unwarranted
presuppositions about how Bacon used the term. His motive appears to lie
in his argument that the faults of scholastic logic lay in lengthy
disputes about meaningless terms. Therefore the first task of scientific
reforms lay in defining terms that really meant something, that refer to
really existing things in nature. So to speak about heat, for example, as
a kind of generalized form, or even worse an occult quality, without
engaging in first, a careful examination of particular instances of this
or that hot thing and the exclusion of apparent but ultimately erroneous
examples of hot things, and then a considered definition of what it means
to be hot, would be just as bad as the wild scholastic debates about
being, substance and passion. Induction is this exclusion. It is a way of
clarifying scientific language. “It is this kind of induction whose help
we must have not only to discover axioms but also to define concepts. (NO
p. 84)” Descartes’ contributions to the tools of science were
incalculably greater as is evident in Note 8 below.
- Bacon wrote before the combined effects of Galilean,
Cartesian and Newtonian science would do away with the need to talk about
forms and simplify the scientific universe of discourse to a few
measurable entities. Thus, from an ontological point
of view, the need for induction in the Baconian sense has been replaced by
a kind of scientific liberalism where entities (individual forms or
natures) are tolerated if they are measurable and required by the theory.
Others are reduced to the basic entities of the theory. Baconian induction
remains mainly of philosophical value. It serves as a worthwhile
methodological caution for philosophers who wish to address issues of
ontology outside the safe confines of natural science. Bacon also
associates forms with the causes for lawlike behavior and what he calls
latent structure; he distinguishes explanation based on a search for forms
from an explanation that looks for final causes (NO pp. 102-103).
This comes down to an essentialist view (NO p. 119) although Bacon
avoids the term “essence.” The term “latent structure” sounds like, and
probably is, the harbinger of the corpuscular theory and the mechanistic
explanations of of natural and physiological phenomena that Descartes did
more than anybody else to advance. Descartes simply drops any concern
about essences in his physical theory. Instead of asking “What is it”
with the attendant assumption that the answer to that question would
reveal a “virtue” that explains, or rather names, an essence's
interactions with other essences, Descartes began to ask a different
question: “How does it work” The difference between these two questions
and their corresponding influence on research is what constitutes the
scientific revolution of the 17th century.
- Bacon simply eschewed first philosophy in favor of
faith and revelation in theological matters, and an apparent agnosticism
regarding the basic categories of the world and of knowledge. Descartes
famously shared religious goals with the schoolmen, but instead of using
their terminology he tries to stay with plain terms like “God” and the
“soul.” He does make some use of the concept of substance, mostly in his
metaphysics.
- Bacon observes that between Aristotle and his time
there was really no science. Bacon and Descartes’ differences with the
schoolmen lay not in disagreement or different answers to shared
questions. Rather, as far as an understanding of the natural world was
concerned, scholastic goals and objectives as well as methods were simply
tossed overboard. If there are such things as paradigm shifts, this was
one. (Cf. NO pp. 60 ff.) Note the rhetoric Bacon and Descartes use
in describing their programs. Bacon’s concept of a new beginning is not
really metaphorical or any kind of trope. Its meaning is literal. But
Bacon uses the term in a lawyerly way with the aim of producing a sort of
oratorical enthusiasm in his readers. Descartes does employ metaphor when
he speaks of clear and solid truths (It is not insignificant that
Descartes was simply the best writer of philosophy since Plato). Today
this rhetoric has fallen on hard times, perhaps because it has served its
purpose. In its place the epistemological Marxism of scientific
revolutions has been imprinted on our brain cells.
- This is not foundationalism in the modern sense made
familiar by Russell and Husserl. For Bacon especially, secure foundations
meant simply doing things right: “… a general Renewal of the sciences and
arts and all human learning, beginning from correct foundations. (p. 2)”
Where he does speak of foundations such that “philosophy and the sciences
may no longer float in the air…(p.5)” he clearly means adopting the method
of experiment and observation and not some sort of hierarchical system
where new propositions are derived from foundational propositions. An
important notion in Bacon’s way of doing things is “degrees of certainty
(p. 28)” in contrast to the absolute certainty required by Descartes (and
Russell and Husserl). The concept of foundationalism in Descartes is more
complex. Descartes does have a concept of unassailable and certain truth.
The foundational propositions on which all further knowledge is built,
however, as he repeats over and over again, are (1) his own existence, (2)
the existence of the soul, (3) the existence of God, (4) the assurance
that God could not deceive him about the conclusions he draws (as e.g. the
existence of material things) that are not already secured by the basic
arguments that secured (1)-(3). Descartes does not say that more specific
propositions (such as those concerning the circulation of blood) are not
subject to revision based on further experiment. In fact, as summarized in
Rule II (Règles, pp. 39 ff.), Descartes is, at least as of 1619,
quite unequivocal that conclusions based on or essentially involving
experience are only probable, that is subject to revision. The only
certain and indubitable results are those of arithmetical and geometric
deductions (Remember Descartes calls (1)-(4) geometric proofs). Nor does
he give examples of other propositions that, like (1)-(3), are also
unassailable without being based on (4). There is another element to
Descartes’ new beginning which, in spirit at least, more closely
approximates Bacon’s attitude. This is the streamlining and sophistication
of mathematical techniques and the application of measurement to
observation and the manipulation of the results of measurement. (Bacon did
not appear to have sufficient appreciation of the importance of
measurement. He may have also had an insufficient appreciation of
mathematics. On p. 79 he says the proper role of mathematics is to limit
natural philosophy, not to generate or beget it. His probable meaning is
that mathematics alone without observation is useless. (Cf. also p. 225.) On
mixing mathematics with metaphysics he says, “…it being the nature of the
mind of man (to the extreme prejudice of knowledge) to delight in the
spacious liberty of generalities, as in a champain region, and not in the
inclosures of particularity….” (p. 200 The Advancement of Learning))
When Descartes talks about secure and unassailable methods he also means
the methods of the geometricians, but his sense of the methods of
geometricians is twofold. First, he simply means the sort of - sometimes
lengthy - deductive chains used by geometricians in deriving theorems from
their axioms, chains that could be constructed as algebraic computations
using his newly devised symbolism. But for Descartes his Cogito and proof
of the existence of God were also examples of geometrical reasoning
although those proofs appear (somewhat incorrectly) to bear little or no relation to either the
type of reasoning employed by Euclid or arithmetical reasoning. (This does
raise the interesting question of what compels assent in a geometric
demonstration. It is often pointed out in defense of the certainty or
necessity of logical laws that we cannot know what someone who denies a
logical law means. The nature of geometrical demonstrations as performed
from Euclid through Fermat are more mysterious. Descartes’ Géométrie
(Cf. his 1637 Géométrie and the
Discours de la méthode pp. 246 ff.) swept
away much of the mystery by reducing “compass and ruler” geometric proofs
to symbolic deductions where the move from one step to the next – through
substitution of terms – is in effect little more than the application of a
logical law. It is important to note that when Descartes says that
geometrical proofs are clear, distinct and unassailable he means the
proofs of his own analytic geometry and not compass and ruler proofs.).
Descartes (Règles pp. 39 ff.) rejects any conclusion involving
experience as not living up to his criterion of certainty. He admits that
the only sciences left worthy of the name are arithmetic and geometry.
Presumably he would not deny that the results of the experiments
concerning light and refraction that he outlines in the Discours
could be revised in the light of new data. So perhaps Descartes would draw
a line between geometrical proofs which are clear and certain in every way
and the results of empirical science that are only certain to the degree
that they are not subject to a sort of universal falsehood such as may be
practiced upon us by a malin génie and not the benevolent God (Cf.
Rule II p. 41 where Descartes asserts that experience can be deceptive
while deduction is not deceptive. The reason arithmetic and geometry are
more certain than experience is that their objects are “pure and simple.”
They do not admit of the errors of experience.). Since the proof of the
existence and benevolence of this God was arrived at by Descartes through
means that he qualifies as geometrical, that proof is clear and certain in
every way. Descartes’ treatment of the natural sciences is less forthcoming about the
strict distinction between probable and certain truths. The Discours de
la Méthode was published in 1637 well after the unpublished Règles were written. The
Discours
summarizes the history of Descartes’ encounters with experimental science,
particularly Harvey and Galileo and so it could be describing a time
roughly posterior to the Règles but contemporaneous to the
groundbreaking publication of the Géométrie. Two points are worth
noting from the Discours. First, the results of the experimental
sciences are not described as merely probable (or indubitable), but “très
certains (p. 178),” make of that what you will. Secondly, the objections
Descartes raises against experimentation are purely practical: the paucity
of his own resources and the unreliability and non-disinterestedness of
communications from other researchers. The Discourse should be
understood as a description of his own intellectual journey, a memoir, so
to speak, and not an actual argument against the sharing of experimental
results. At the end of the day Descartes’ introduction of extension,
figure and motion as the basic concepts of science fundamentally changes
not only the Aristotelian substance/accident model as a basis for
scientific research but also Bacon’s
project of search for essences or simple natures through his exclusionist
model of induction.
- Bacon provides the more thorough and detailed
criticism of scholasticism (Again neither Bacon nor Descartes give
sufficient – or any – credit to Galileo who began the fight against the
Aristotelian syllogism and framed the terms of the attack): (1)
Scholastics are not so much interested in the truth as having their school
prevail over the others. Those who do advocate disinterested inquiry have
no method and end up in aimless investigation. They are concerned only
with what others have said; they do not pay attention to the things
themselves. (2) The scholastics abstract too quickly from particular
instances. They rely on syllogistic reasoning. There is nothing wrong with
the conclusion of a well-formed syllogism. (“…no one could doubt that
things which agree in a middle term, agree also with each other (which has
a kind of mathematical certainty)….(NO p. 16)” (Cf. also Bk I,
Aphorism XIX) The fraud in scholastic syllogistic disputes comes not from
the form of reasoning but from the terms to which the reasoning is
applied. These terms are “badly or carelessly abstracted from things…;”
they are “vague and not defined with sufficiently clear outlines.”
Scholastic terms are largely meaningless. The culprit is hasty
abstraction. “For the way the thing has been normally done until now is to
leap immediately from sense and particulars to the most general
propositions...; then to derive everything else from them by means of
intermediate propositions….” (By inclining to derive the certain
propositions of science as a body from his four fundamental metaphysical
propositions, there is a way that Descartes’ procedure is liable to the
very same criticism, at least in the transition from metaphysical
conclusions to natural philosophy.) Logic can fix errors in reasoning but
it is positively harmful as a way of discovering truths. In today’s terminology we would say
that logic by itself does not provide us with true simple propositions
about nature. “It compels assent without reference to things (NO
p.35)” (3) The concept of a final cause is a fanciful human invention and
has nothing to do with nature. In The Advancement of Learning Bacon
calls scholasticism “contentious learning” that leads to “vain
altercations” (p. 138). In contrast, Bacon’s method elicits axioms
gradually, step by step, so the broadest generalizations come at the end
of the process and not at the beginning. It begins with an analysis of
experience by means of “appropriate exclusions and rejections (p.17).”
- Bacon’s advocacy of a community of researchers such
as came to be exemplified in the Royal Society is the third key element of
the new instauration along with experimentation and induction. It is
interesting to contrast this with Descartes’ apparently diffident attitude
to sharing his research or benefiting from the findings of others, such
that in the Discours he seems to be as much concerned
with convincing himself that he should publish as with anything else.
There is more to the contrast than a simple difference of temperament or
the relative historical position of the two men vis à vis the condemnation
of Galileo. Indeed Descartes lived a partially recluse life and placed
great value on his own repos. Bacon was an active statesman and
lawyer, whereas Descartes’ only profession, before he acquired sufficient
resources to concentrate only on philosophy, was a sort of military
tourism. Bacon the
gregarious attacked scholasticism at length from an evident esprit de
parti, while Descartes did not engage in polemic (notwithstanding his
disputes with individual theologians) although he shared
Bacon’s view on scholasticism and syllogism. The essence of the Royal
Society was cooperation, while Descartes’ most frequent interaction with
his peers came in the form of dispute as evidenced in the celebrated
Objections and Replies to the Méditations. Bacon’s explicitly
stated ends were also not entirely shared by Descartes. Bacon wanted to do
good for mankind by increasing knowledge and creating technology that
would improve life. Descartes was more concerned with a personal assurance
for his beliefs, both theological and scientific. These contrasting
personality types find echoes throughout the history of science. Generally
the day to day work of experimentation and data collection falls to the
Baconian personality. The great counter experiments that undermine
prevailing theories come from a Baconian community. The breakthrough
theories, however, that establish new paradigms and change science forever
are often the work of isolated Cartesian souls. We need only think of the
secretive Newton in his Cambridge rooms who didn’t even see the need to
publish many of his most important discoveries. Even Einstein developed
relativity largely outside the official scientific community. Experimental research is Baconian;
mathematics is Cartesian.
- French has a single word, “expérience,” for
both “observation” and “experiment.” And Descartes’ views on the value of
experiment were not entirely consistent. In Latin experientia and
experimentum can also both mean “experience,” i.e. observation, or “experiment” which
leads to ambiguities in Bacon. But Bacon’s unequivocal passages where he
says that the unaided senses are faulty and he talks about substitutions,
corrections and instruments to aid the senses, show he was aiming at the
essential in the distinction between experience and experiment or
controlled observation. Incidentally the undergraduate truism that
Descartes the rationalist abjured experiment and observation in favor of
purely speculative theories about nature is not only false, it is absurd.
It appears to have arisen from some sort of anglo-positivist jingoistic
myth-making.
- It is interesting to note the terms that Bacon
identifies as “abstracted from nature without care. (NO p. 35)”
They are more or less the Aristotelian categories: substance, quality,
action, passion, being. To these he adds a mixed bag of terms that
retained importance as scientific concepts. Matter, element, attraction
and repulsion became the basic concepts of physics (although we must not
forget that the only thing that distinguishes gravitation, a concept that
Newton was never entirely comfortable with, from scholastic occult
qualities is that gravitational effects are measurable). Heavy, light,
dense, rare, wet, dry are secondary qualities that could be rephrased
using the basic concepts of physics. Bacon’s rejection of form is
inconsistent since in Part II of The New Organon (p. 128 and
passim) Bacon equates forms with simple natures. In contrast man, dog,
dove and the immediate perceptions of hot, cold white and black should be
the starting point of sciences, even though the observations of these
things can also be misleading.
- Descartes’ discourse on rainbows (p. 230) is a
genuine example of an experiment that he introduces by saying how it will
show how his method leads to new discoveries and explanations. It is
unclear from the text itself whether what Descartes writes about the
senses and the refraction of light is based on actual experiments or
thought experiments (pp. 180 ff.). Note how Descartes seems to contradict
what he says regarding the value of experiments in the Fifth Part of the
Discours proper.
|